000 02920nam a22002057a 4500
003 PMNP
005 20250619090821.0
008 250619b |||||||| |||| 00| 0 eng d
020 _a9781107162792
040 _aPMNP
_beng
_cKutubkhanah Diraja
082 _a320.44
100 _93603
_aBoucoyannis, Deborah
245 _aKings as Judges:
_bPower, Justice, and the Origins of Parliaments /
_cDeborah Boucoyannis,
260 _aUnited Kingdom
_bCambridge University Press
_c2021
300 _a386p
520 _aThis remarkable book extends the ‘historical turn’ in political science into the very heartlands of medieval political and constitutional history, with its question-centred account of the origins of parliaments. In a significant instance of what she calls ‘normative/empirical inversion’ (e.g. p. 10), Deborah Boucoyannis finds the key to durable, polity-wide representative institutions, and, by association, to ‘constitutionalism’ (e.g. p. 33), in strong medieval monarchies—above all, that of England—and in their capacity to compel the attendance of their strongest subjects, to extract taxation from them and to force them to engage with other classes in society in pursuit of common interests. Power, then, is at the centre of the thesis, but justice is important too: parliaments were most successful when they were embedded in the judicial structures of medieval states—as high courts, but also as the locales in which judicially-enforceable legislation was created. In the English case (and it is that case which is most fully developed in the book), the far-reaching power of the common law enabled the king both to attract and to insist on the attendance of elites at parliament, to bind subjects to the fulfilment of what was agreed there, and to create meaningful statutes which his judges would enforce; by a process of ‘functional layering’ (p. 43 ff.), other roles were added to an institution whose regular and basic purposes were associated with justice. So it is that Boucoyannis challenges some of the more prominent arguments of historically minded social scientists (and some historians): representative institutions did not arise in the first place from bargaining over taxation, but from the administration of law and justice; constitutional rights were sought more as a response to overweening royal power than as a benefit to taxpaying classes; the capacity of the state to compel the nobles was more important for constitutionalism than any dialogue with towns (merchants and townsmen sought sectoral privileges, not collective ones); regularity of representation arose from ‘compellence’, not the desire for liberty. In all, instead of ‘no taxation without representation’, we should think in terms of ‘no taxation of elites, no representative institutions’ (ch. 6).
650 0 _9437
_aPolitical science
942 _2ddc
_cBK
_n0
999 _c3424
_d3424